Talk:PlanetPhysics/Axiomatic Theories of Metacategories and Supercategories
Add topicAppearance
Original TeX Content from PlanetPhysics Archive
[edit source]%%% This file is part of PlanetPhysics snapshot of 2011-09-01
%%% Primary Title: axiomatic theories of metacategories and supercategories
%%% Primary Category Code: 00.
%%% Filename: AxiomaticTheoriesOfMetacategoriesAndSupercategories.tex
%%% Version: 10
%%% Owner: bci1
%%% Author(s): bci1
%%% PlanetPhysics is released under the GNU Free Documentation License.
%%% You should have received a file called fdl.txt along with this file.
%%% If not, please write to gnu@gnu.org.
\documentclass[12pt]{article}
\pagestyle{empty}
\setlength{\paperwidth}{8.5in}
\setlength{\paperheight}{11in}
\setlength{\topmargin}{0.00in}
\setlength{\headsep}{0.00in}
\setlength{\headheight}{0.00in}
\setlength{\evensidemargin}{0.00in}
\setlength{\oddsidemargin}{0.00in}
\setlength{\textwidth}{6.5in}
\setlength{\textheight}{9.00in}
\setlength{\voffset}{0.00in}
\setlength{\hoffset}{0.00in}
\setlength{\marginparwidth}{0.00in}
\setlength{\marginparsep}{0.00in}
\setlength{\parindent}{0.00in}
\setlength{\parskip}{0.15in}
\usepackage{html}
% there are many more packages, add them here as you need
% define commands here
\usepackage{amsmath, amssymb, amsfonts, amsthm, amscd, latexsym}
\usepackage{xypic}
\usepackage[mathscr]{eucal}
\theoremstyle{plain}
\newtheorem{lemma}{Lemma}[section]
\newtheorem{proposition}{Proposition}[section]
\newtheorem{theorem}{Theorem}[section]
\newtheorem{corollary}{Corollary}[section]
\theoremstyle{definition}
\newtheorem{definition}{Definition}[section]
\newtheorem{example}{Example}[section]
%\theoremstyle{remark}
\newtheorem{remark}{Remark}[section]
\newtheorem*{notation}{Notation}
\newtheorem*{claim}{Claim}
\renewcommand{\thefootnote}{\ensuremath{\fnsymbol{footnote%%@
}}}
\numberwithin{equation}{section}
\newcommand{\Ad}{{\rm Ad}}
\newcommand{\Aut}{{\rm Aut}}
\newcommand{\Cl}{{\rm Cl}}
\newcommand{\Co}{{\rm Co}}
\newcommand{\DES}{{\rm DES}}
\newcommand{\Diff}{{\rm Diff}}
\newcommand{\Dom}{{\rm Dom}}
\newcommand{\Hol}{{\rm Hol}}
\newcommand{\Mon}{{\rm Mon}}
\newcommand{\Hom}{{\rm Hom}}
\newcommand{\Ker}{{\rm Ker}}
\newcommand{\Ind}{{\rm Ind}}
\newcommand{\IM}{{\rm Im}}
\newcommand{\Is}{{\rm Is}}
\newcommand{\ID}{{\rm id}}
\newcommand{\GL}{{\rm GL}}
\newcommand{\Iso}{{\rm Iso}}
\newcommand{\Sem}{{\rm Sem}}
\newcommand{\St}{{\rm St}}
\newcommand{\Sym}{{\rm Sym}}
\newcommand{\SU}{{\rm SU}}
\newcommand{\Tor}{{\rm Tor}}
\newcommand{\U}{{\rm U}}
\newcommand{\A}{\mathcal A}
\newcommand{\Ce}{\mathcal C}
\newcommand{\D}{\mathcal D}
\newcommand{\E}{\mathcal E}
\newcommand{\F}{\mathcal F}
\newcommand{\G}{\mathcal G}
\newcommand{\Q}{\mathcal Q}
\newcommand{\R}{\mathcal R}
\newcommand{\cS}{\mathcal S}
\newcommand{\cU}{\mathcal U}
\newcommand{\W}{\mathcal W}
\newcommand{\bA}{\mathbb{A}}
\newcommand{\bB}{\mathbb{B}}
\newcommand{\bC}{\mathbb{C}}
\newcommand{\bD}{\mathbb{D}}
\newcommand{\bE}{\mathbb{E}}
\newcommand{\bF}{\mathbb{F}}
\newcommand{\bG}{\mathbb{G}}
\newcommand{\bK}{\mathbb{K}}
\newcommand{\bM}{\mathbb{M}}
\newcommand{\bN}{\mathbb{N}}
\newcommand{\bO}{\mathbb{O}}
\newcommand{\bP}{\mathbb{P}}
\newcommand{\bR}{\mathbb{R}}
\newcommand{\bV}{\mathbb{V}}
\newcommand{\bZ}{\mathbb{Z}}
\newcommand{\bfE}{\mathbf{E}}
\newcommand{\bfX}{\mathbf{X}}
\newcommand{\bfY}{\mathbf{Y}}
\newcommand{\bfZ}{\mathbf{Z}}
\renewcommand{\O}{\Omega}
\renewcommand{\o}{\omega}
\newcommand{\vp}{\varphi}
\newcommand{\vep}{\varepsilon}
\newcommand{\diag}{{\rm diag}}
\newcommand{\grp}{{\mathbb G}}
\newcommand{\dgrp}{{\mathbb D}}
\newcommand{\desp}{{\mathbb D^{\rm{es}}}}
\newcommand{\Geod}{{\rm Geod}}
\newcommand{\geod}{{\rm geod}}
\newcommand{\hgr}{{\mathbb H}}
\newcommand{\mgr}{{\mathbb M}}
\newcommand{\ob}{{\rm Ob}}
\newcommand{\obg}{{\rm Ob(\mathbb G)}}
\newcommand{\obgp}{{\rm Ob(\mathbb G')}}
\newcommand{\obh}{{\rm Ob(\mathbb H)}}
\newcommand{\Osmooth}{{\Omega^{\infty}(X,*)}}
\newcommand{\ghomotop}{{\rho_2^{\square}}}
\newcommand{\gcalp}{{\mathbb G(\mathcal P)}}
\newcommand{\rf}{{R_{\mathcal F}}}
\newcommand{\glob}{{\rm glob}}
\newcommand{\loc}{{\rm loc}}
\newcommand{\TOP}{{\rm TOP}}
\newcommand{\wti}{\widetilde}
\newcommand{\what}{\widehat}
\renewcommand{\a}{\alpha}
\newcommand{\be}{\beta}
\newcommand{\ga}{\gamma}
\newcommand{\Ga}{\Gamma}
\newcommand{\de}{\delta}
\newcommand{\del}{\partial}
\newcommand{\ka}{\kappa}
\newcommand{\si}{\sigma}
\newcommand{\ta}{\tau}
\newcommand{\lra}{{\longrightarrow}}
\newcommand{\ra}{{\rightarrow}}
\newcommand{\rat}{{\rightarrowtail}}
\newcommand{\oset}[1]{\overset {#1}{\ra}}
\newcommand{\osetl}[1]{\overset {#1}{\lra}}
\newcommand{\hr}{{\hookrightarrow}}
\begin{document}
\subsection{Introduction}
This is a topic on the axioms of \htmladdnormallink{categories}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Cod.html}, metacategories and supercategories
that are relevant, respectively, to mathematics and meta-mathematics.
Lawvere's \htmladdnormallink{elementary theory of abstract categories}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Formula.html} (\htmladdnormallink{ETAC}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/ETACAxioms.html}) provides an axiomatic construction of the theory of categories and \htmladdnormallink{functors}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/TrivialGroupoid.html}. Intuitively, with this terminology and axioms, a category is meant to be any structure which is a direct interpretation of ETAC. A functor is then understood to be a triple consisting of two such categories and of a rule F (`the functor') which assigns to each arrow or \htmladdnormallink{morphism}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/TrivialGroupoid.html} x of the first category, a unique morphism, written as `F(x)' of the second category, in such a way that the usual two conditions on both \htmladdnormallink{objects}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/TrivialGroupoid.html} and arrows in the standard functor definition are fulfilled --the functor is well behaved, i.e., it carries object \htmladdnormallink{identities}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Cod.html} to image object identities, and \htmladdnormallink{commutative diagrams}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Commutativity.html} to image commmutative \htmladdnormallink{diagrams}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/TrivialGroupoid.html} of the corresponding image objects and image morphisms. At the next level, one then defines \htmladdnormallink{natural transformations}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/VariableCategory2.html} or functorial morphisms between functors as meta-level abbreviated \htmladdnormallink{formulas}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Formula.html} and equations pertaining to commutative diagrams of the distinct images of two functors acting on both objects and morphisms. As the name indicates natural transformations are also well--behaved in terms of the ETAC equations that are satisfied by natural transformations.
\subsection{ETAS and ETAC}
Categories were defined in refs. \cite{LW1,LW2} as mathematical interpretations of the `elementary theory of abstract categories' (ETAC). One can generalize the theory of categories to higher dimensions-- as in \htmladdnormallink{higher dimensional algebra}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/HigherDimensionalAlgebra2.html} (\htmladdnormallink{HDA}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/2Groupoid2.html})-- by defining multiple \htmladdnormallink{composition laws}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Identity2.html} and allowing higher dimensional, functorial morphisms of several variables to be employed in such higher dimensional structures. Thus, one can introduce an elementary theory of supercategories (\htmladdnormallink{ETAS}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/ETACAxioms.html};(\cite{ICB3,ICB1}) as a natural extension of Lawvere's ETAC theory to higher dimensions (\cite{BGB2}). Then, supercategories can be defined as mathematical interpretations of the \htmladdnormallink{ETAS axioms}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/ETACAxioms.html} as in ref.\cite{ICB3}.
\begin{definition}
A concrete \emph{metagraph} $\mathcal{M}_G$ consists of objects, $A, B, C,$...
and arrows $f, g, h,$... between objects, and two \htmladdnormallink{operations}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Cod.html} as follows:
\begin{itemize}
\item a {\em \htmladdnormallink{domain}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Bijective.html} operation}, $dom$, which assigns to each arrow $f$ an object $A~ =~dom ~f$
\item a {\em \htmladdnormallink{codomain}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Bijective.html} operation}, $cod$, which assigns to each arrow $f$ an object $B~ = ~cod ~f,$
represented as $f: A \to B$ or $A \stackrel{f}{\longrightarrow} B$
\end{itemize}
\end{definition}
\begin{remark}
Related \htmladdnormallink{concepts}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/PreciseIdea.html} to the general notion of a supercategory recalled above can also be rendered graphically on a \htmladdnormallink{computer}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Program3.html} as a
multigraph or a \emph{\htmladdnormallink{hypergraph}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/SimpleIncidenceStructure2.html}}. More generally,
the class of metagraphs can be also defined as a specific class of supercategories.
On the other hand, a \htmladdnormallink{supercomputer}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/SupercomputerArchitercture.html} architecture
and operating \htmladdnormallink{system}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/SimilarityAndAnalogousSystemsDynamicAdjointnessAndTopologicalEquivalence.html} software are examples of realizations of relatively simple, or lower dimensional supercategories,
as explained in further detail in the next subsections.
\end{remark}
\section{ETAS Axioms:}
\begin{enumerate}
\item \textbf{(S1)}. All symbols, formulas and the eight axioms defined in ETAC are, respectively, also ETAS symbols, formulas and axioms; thus, for any letters $x, y, i, u, A, B$, and \emph{unary \htmladdnormallink{function}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Bijective.html}} symbols $\Delta_0$ and $\Delta_1$, and \emph{composition laws} $\Gamma_i$, the following are defined as \emph{formulas}: $\Delta_0 (x) = A$,$\Delta_1 (x) = B$, $\Gamma (x,y;u)$, and $ x = y$.
The above formulas are to be, respectively, interpreted as ``$A$ is the domain of $x$", ``$B$ is the codomain, or range, of $x$", ``$u$ is the \htmladdnormallink{composition}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Cod.html} $x$ followed by $y$", and ``$x$ equals $y$"; letters $i, j, k, l, m, ...$ are to be interpreted as ``either element, set or class ($ C$ ) indices". An example of valid ETAC and ETAS formula is a couple or pair of two letters written as ``$(x,y)$"; a more general related example is that of Cartesian or direct products ${\Pi}_{i ~ in ~ C}$.
\item \textbf{(S2)}. There are several composition laws defined in ETAS (as distinct from ETAC where there is only one composition law for each interpretation in any specific \htmladdnormallink{type}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Bijective.html} of category ); such multiple composition laws $\Gamma_i$, with $i ~in~ C$ are interpreted as ``definitions of multiple (specific) mathematical structures, within the same supercategory $\mathcal{\S}$" .
\end{enumerate}
In the case of general algebras, the multiple composition laws are interpreted as \emph{``definitions of \htmladdnormallink{algebraic structures}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/TrivialGroupoid.html}"}, (whereas \emph{\htmladdnormallink{categorical algebra}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/CategoryOfLogicAlgebras.html}} is interpreted as being ``defined by a single composition law
${\Gamma}_1 = \circ $ (or ``*" for -involution or $C^*$ -algebras )". An ETAC structure is thus identified by the singleton $\left\{1 \right\}$ index set.
\subsection{Examples of supercategories}
Pseudographs, hypergraphs, 1-categories, categorical algebras, $2$-categories, $n$-categories, \htmladdnormallink{functor categories}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/TrivialGroupoid.html}, \htmladdnormallink{super-categories}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/SuperCategory6.html}, super-diagrams, functor supercatgeories, \htmladdnormallink{double groupoids}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/ThinEquivalence.html}, \htmladdnormallink{double categories}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/HorizontalIdentities.html}, organismic supercategories, self-replicating \htmladdnormallink{quantum automata}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/QuantumComputers.html}, standard Heyting \htmladdnormallink{topos}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/GrothendieckTopos.html}, generalized $LM_n$-logic algebra topoi, \htmladdnormallink{double algebroids}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/GeneralizedSuperalgebras.html}, super-categories of double algebroids, and any higher dimensional algebra (HDA) are examples of supercategories of various orders.
\subsection{Graphic example of a supercategory}
A pictorial \htmladdnormallink{representation}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/CategoricalGroupRepresentation.html} of a particular class of metagraphs --the class of multigraphs, $M_g$-- is also useful as a visual or `geometric' (or \htmladdnormallink{topological}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/CoIntersections.html}) representation of a specific example of a supercategory defined over the topological space of the multigraph with the composition operations of the supercategory heteromorphisms defined, in this case of the multigraph, by the concatenations of the multigraph vertices in $n$ dimensions for a finite , $n$-dimensional multigraph that can be graphically rendered on a computer.
\subsection{Metagraphs and Metacategories}
\begin{definition}
A more recent version of Lawvere's axioms was presented by MacLane (2000) in which a \emph{metagraph} is first defined as a structure consisting of \emph{objects} $a,b,c,...x,y,z$,
\emph{arrows} $f, g, h, ...$, and two \emph{operations}-- the Domain (which assigns to each arrow $f$ an object
$a=dom~ f$), and a Codomain (which assigns to each arrow $f$ an object $b= cod~ f$. Such
operations can be readily represented by displaying $f$ as an actual arrow $. \to.$
starting at the $dom ~ f$ and ending at $cod ~ f$, $f: a \to b$. With this pictorial, or `geometric'
representation, a finite number of arrows is depicted as a \emph{finite \htmladdnormallink{graph}{http://planetphysics.us/encyclopedia/Cod.html}}.
Then, one defines a \emph{metacategory} as a \emph{metagraph} with two additional operations, \emph{Identity}
and \emph{Composition}(viz. \cite{SML2k}). \emph{Identity} assigns to each object $a$ an arrow $id_a =
1_a: a \to a$. A $composition$ operation assigns to each pair of arrows $(f,g)$ with $dom ~g = cod~ f$ an arrow
called their composite, $g \circ f : dom~ f \to cod~ g$.
\end{definition}
\begin{thebibliography}{99}
\bibitem{ICB3}
I.C. Baianu: 1970, Organismic Supercategories: II. On Multistable Systems. \emph{Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics}, \textbf{32}: 539-561.
\bibitem{ICB1}
I.C. Baianu : 1971a, Organismic Supercategories and Qualitative Dynamics of Systems. \emph{Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics}, \textbf{33} (3), 339--354.
\bibitem{ICB6}
I.C. Baianu: 1977, A Logical Model of Genetic Activities in \L ukasiewicz Algebras: The Non-linear Theory. \emph{Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics}, \textbf{39}: 249-258.
\bibitem{ICB7}
I.C. Baianu: 1980, Natural Transformations of Organismic Structures. \emph{Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics}
\textbf{42}: 431-446.
\bibitem{BBGG1}
I.C. Baianu, Brown R., J. F. Glazebrook, and Georgescu G.: 2006, Complex Nonlinear Biodynamics in
Categories, Higher Dimensional Algebra and \L ukasiewicz--Moisil Topos: Transformations of
Neuronal, Genetic and Neoplastic networks, \emph{Axiomathes} \textbf{16} Nos. 1--2, 65--122.
\bibitem{BHS2}
R. Brown R, P.J. Higgins, and R. Sivera.: \emph{``Non-Abelian Algebraic Topology''},{\em (vol. 2. in preparation)}.
(2008).
\bibitem{BGB2}
R. Brown, J. F. Glazebrook and I. C. Baianu: A categorical and higher dimensional algebra framework for complex systems and spacetime structures, \emph{Axiomathes} \textbf{17}:409--493.
(2007).
\bibitem{BS}
R. Brown and C.B. Spencer: Double groupoids and crossed modules,
\emph{Cahiers Top. G\'eom.Diff.} \textbf{17} (1976), 343--362.
\bibitem{LW1}
W.F. Lawvere: 1963. Functorial Semantics of Algebraic Theories. \emph{Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA}, 50: 869--872
\bibitem{LW2}
W. F. Lawvere: 1966. The Category of Categories as a Foundation for Mathematics. , In {\em Proc. Conf. Categorical Algebra--La Jolla}, 1965, Eilenberg, S et al., eds. Springer --Verlag: Berlin, Heidelberg and New York, pp. 1--20.
\bibitem{LO68}
L. L\"ofgren: 1968. On Axiomatic Explanation of Complete Self--Reproduction. \emph{Bull. Math. Biophysics},
\textbf{30}: 317--348.
\bibitem{SML2k}
S. Mac Lane. 2000. Ch.1: Axioms for Categories, in \emph{Categories for the Working Mathematician}. Springer: Berlin, 2nd Edition.
\end{thebibliography}
\end{document}